Naive set theory: Size of a set
The Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein theorem
For two sets \(X\) and \(Y\), we say that the cardinality of \(X\) is less than or equal to the cardinality of \(Y\), or that the equipotency of \(X\) is less than or equal to the equipotency of \(Y\), or that \(Y\) is at least as large as \(X\), or that \(X\) is not larger than \(Y\), if there exists an injective function from \(X\) to \(Y\). We write: \(X\preccurlyeq Y\).
We say that the cardinality of \(X\) is less than the cardinality of \(Y\), or that the equipotency of \(X\) is less than the equipotency of \(Y\), or that \(Y\) is greater than \(X\), or that \(X\) is less than \(Y\), if there exists an injective function from \(X\) to \(Y\) but no bijection from \(X\) to \(Y\). In other words, \(X\preccurlyeq Y\), but \(X\ncong Y\). We write: \(X\prec Y\).
With the above definitions, we can also say that a set \(X\) is countable if \(X\preccurlyeq \mathbb{N}\) and uncountable if \(\mathbb{N}\prec X\).
Cantor's Theorem \(X\prec{\Large\wp}(\mathbb{X})\) for every set \(X\).
The following Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein theorem provides a convenient way to demonstrate the equipotency of sets, because one no longer needs to find a bijective function between two sets, but it suffices to find two injective functions from one set to the other and vice versa.
Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein Theorem Let \(X\) and \(Y\) be two sets. If there exists an injective function from \(X\) to \(Y\) and there exists an injective function from \(Y\) to \(X\), then there exists a bijective function from \(X\) to \(Y\) and the two sets are thus equipotent. In formula language:
For two sets \(X\) and \(Y\): \(\text{If }X\preccurlyeq Y\text{ and }Y\preccurlyeq X\text{ then } X\cong Y\).
Corollary The open and closed intervals \((0,1)\) and \([0,1]\) in \(\mathbb{R}\) are equipotent. In formula form: \((0,1)\cong [0,1]\).
\(\mathbb{R}\times \mathbb{R} \cong \mathbb{R}\).